top of page

The Scales of Justice: Law, Morality, and the Vigilantism

  • Shiv Mehendiratta
  • Mar 23
  • 4 min read

When the machinery of law grinds to a halt, leaving justice unserved,

individuals throughout history and fiction have stepped into the breach. From

Robin Hood’s defiance of corrupt sheriffs to the extralegal retribution of

Sophocles’ Antigone, the impulse to act outside legal systems raises a

profound question: is it ever justified to take justice into one’s own hands? This

essay contends that while legal systems are essential for societal order, their

failures, whether through corruption, inadequacy, or moral blindness, can

necessitate individual action, provided such acts align with a higher moral

framework. Justice, law, and morality are intertwined yet distinct, and their

tensions reveal both the limits of legal obedience and the ethical demands of

extraordinary circumstances.


At its essence, justice is the quest for fairness and the correction of wrongs.

Law, in the ideal sense, acts as its tool, turning moral values into enforceable

regulations. However, morality transcends legal codes, grounded in human

conscience and universal principles such as dignity and equity. The interplay

among these three concepts is dynamic. Law aims to institutionalize justice,

while morality evaluates and influences both. When legal systems succeed,

they coincide with moral justice, exemplified by significant changes like the end

of slavery. However, when it fails, through systemic bias as in Jim Crow-era

America or through inaction as in the face of genocide, individuals face a

dilemma. They must either obey the law and tolerate injustice or act beyond it

to uphold morality.


Historical examples illuminate this tension. Consider the Underground Railroad

in the nineteenth-century United States. Enslaved individuals and abolitionists

defied the Fugitive Slave Act, a legally binding statute, to liberate thousands

from bondage. Their actions were illegal, yet few would dispute their moral

righteousness. Harriet Tubman, a conductor of this network, risked her life not

because the law permitted it but because justice demanded it. Similarly, in

Nazi-occupied Europe, resistance fighters and civilians hid Jews from the

Gestapo, violating collaborationist laws to preserve human lives. These cases

suggest that when legal systems entrench or enable injustice, extralegal action

becomes not only defensible but obligatory.


The tension between justice and law is also explored in cinema, particularly in

the works of Alfred Hitchcock and films like Les Diaboliques and Psycho. These

films present characters who take matters into their own hands, often in morally

ambiguous situations. In Les Diaboliques, two women conspire to murder a

tyrannical man, believing the legal system offers no relief. Their act, though

legally reprehensible, invites audiences to question whether justice can exist

outside legal frameworks. Hitchcock’s films, including Psycho, often portray

a world where institutional authority fails to protect the innocent, forcing


individuals into morally complex decisions. Scholars have debated the

extent to which these films critique the justice system or merely explore human

psychology in crisis. These narratives add to the discourse on law and

morality by illustrating the dangers and necessity of taking justice into one’s

own hands.


Fiction, too, probes this moral frontier. In Victor Hugo’s Les Misérables, Jean

Valjean steals bread to feed his starving family, an act condemned by law but

compelled by survival and compassion. Hugo contrasts Valjean’s petty crime

with the rigid legalism of Inspector Javert, whose obsession with enforcement

blinds him to mercy. The novel implies that justice transcends law when the

latter ossifies into an instrument of oppression. Likewise, Batman, the caped

crusader of Gotham, operates outside a corrupt legal system to combat crime,

embodying a vigilante ethos that prioritizes results over procedure. These

narratives romanticize the outlaw, but they also challenge us to weigh the

legitimacy of their cause against the chaos of unchecked individualism.


Yet, the case for vigilantism is not absolute. Law exists to temper subjective

morality with objective order. If every individual became their own judge and

executioner, society could descend into anarchy, where personal vendettas

masquerade as justice. The 1881 lynching of cattle rustlers in Montana by

vigilantes, for instance, began as a response to weak law enforcement but

devolved into mob violence, claiming innocent lives. This dark side of extralegal

action underscores a critical caveat. Taking justice into one’s own hands is

justifiable only when grounded in universal moral principles such as the

preservation of life or the defense of the powerless and executed with restraint.


Philosophers offer frameworks to navigate this dilemma. John Locke argued

that in a state of nature, individuals have a natural right to punish wrongdoers, a

right ceded to the state in a social contract [5]. When the state fails its end of

the bargain, protecting life, liberty, and property, Locke implies a reversion to

that natural right. Conversely, Immanuel Kant’s categorical imperative demands

that actions be universalizable [6]. A vigilante must ask whether their act of

defiance, if replicated by all, would uphold justice without unraveling society.

These perspectives suggest a conditional justification. Extralegal action is

permissible when law betrays its purpose, but it must mirror the impartiality and

proportionality law ideally embodies.


The Rwandan Genocide of 1994 provides a modern crucible for this argument.

As Hutu extremists slaughtered Tutsis, the international legal system faltered,

with the United Nations paralyzed by bureaucracy. Ordinary Rwandans, like

Paul Rusesabagina, sheltered hundreds in his hotel, defying genocidal decrees.

His actions, technically illegal under the regime’s edicts, saved lives where law

offered no recourse. Rusesabagina’s story, dramatized in Hotel Rwanda, affirms

that when legal systems collapse under the weight of their own cowardice or

complicity, moral agents must act, provided their intent is restorative, not

vengeful.


Critics might argue that bypassing law undermines its legitimacy, inviting a

slippery slope where every grievance justifies rebellion. This concern is valid

but overstated. Legal systems derive legitimacy from their ability to deliver

justice. When they fail spectacularly, as in Rwanda or apartheid South Africa,

their authority erodes regardless. The greater risk lies in passivity, where blind

obedience perpetuates harm. Morality, not law, remains the final arbiter, and

individuals must sometimes wield it as a scalpel to excise injustice from the

body politic.


In conclusion, taking justice into one’s own hands is justified when legal

systems fail to uphold their moral mandate, provided such actions adhere to

universal ethical standards. History and fiction alike demonstrate that law is a

tool, not a god. When it breaks, the burden of justice falls to those brave

enough to mend it. This does not mean abandoning legal obedience altogether.

Order is a prerequisite for civilization, but in rare, dire circumstances, morality

demands defiance. The Underground Railroad, Antigone, and Rusesabagina

remind us that justice is not the law’s monopoly. It is humanity’s inheritance, to

be claimed when the scales tip too far from equity.

1 Comment


Irham A. Kristiawan
Apr 17

I love this essay. Especially in the way that it does not romanticise vigilantism - and therefore chaos, a slippery slope to which many authors have unfortunately fallen. Yet it exposes the flaws of law, even if made with the greatest of intentions.


Truly, I don't believe in holding laws rigidly. Laws are tools, an entirely separate entity from objective morality. But as the nature of philosophy is that its concepts are often abstract and unprovable, we humans are tragically not equipped to ever discover what that true objective morality is. Hence, we've created laws - a tool to interpret it the best way that we can.


You must obey the law until the law disobeys humanity.

Like

Be notified of new publications

Get to know Jakarta Philosophy

Follow us to engage with thoughtful, student-driven explorations of philosophy and critical ideas.

  • Instagram
  • LinkedIn
goatlogo-removebg_edited_edited_edited.p

© 2025 Jakarta Philosophy. All rights reserved.

bottom of page